Conference: Imagination in the History of Philosophy
phantasia, imaginatio, imagination: from Plato to Hume
October 9-11, 2025
Organisers: Attila Hangai & Dániel Attila Kovács & Dániel Schmal
Conference Topic
The conference traces the notion of mental representation (phantasia, imaginatio) in ancient, medieval, and early modern philosophy. The papers cover various aspects of the notion, including its role in cognitive activities – e.g., sense-perception, memory, imagination, dreaming, discursive thinking – as well as in moral psychology, especially as the bearer of motivational content both in humans and in other animals. By tracing the development of the notion from its ancient origins through its medieval reception until early modernity, we expect to gain a new perspective on the history of ideas of human cognition.
Program:
8:45 – 9:00:
Welcome
SESSION 1 – Chair: István Bodnár (CEU & ELTE)
9:00 – 9:45
Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi (London): Elpis, Reasoning and phantasmata in the Philebus
9:45 – 10:30
Diego Zucca (Sassari): Plato's Account of Phantasia and Aristotle's Criticism of It
SESSION 2 – Chair: Attila Hangai (RCH, Budapest)
11:00 – 11:45
Robert Roreitner (Prague): Dependence of Thought on phantasia in Aristotle's De Anima
11:45 – 12:30
Zihao Guo (Oslo): Contemplating the Image: Aristotle on Attention and Representation in Practical Deliberation
Lunch Break: 12:30 – 14:00
SESSION 3 – Chair: ()
14:00 – 14:45
Vasia Vergouli (Thessaloniki): Artistic Representation and Character Formation in Aristotle’s Politics
14:45 – 15:30
Attila Németh (RCH, Budapest): Epicurus' Notion of prolēpsis
SESSION 4 – Chair: Dániel Attila Kovács (RCH, Budapest)
16:00 – 16:45
Riin Sirkel (Tartu & Vermont): The Role of Imagination in the Stoic Practice of premeditatio malorum
16:45 – 17:30
László Bene (RCH, Budapest): Phantasia in Plotinus’ Theory of Action
CONFERENCE DINNER – TBA
Abstracts
In the Philebus, Socrates and Protarchus engage in a conversation about what makes one’s life good (11d, 21). The two obvious contestants are pleasures and knowledge, but it turns out that neither one is capable of making a life good on its own. What is needed is, instead, a mixture. This focus on the good a whole life, as opposed to momentary goods, prepares us for the attention the dialogue pays to how we engage with the past, the present and the future, particularly with respect to pleasure. In this paper, I focus on how the Philebus depicts our cognitive engagement with the future. I argue that this cognitive engagement involves reasoning and forming phantasmata, both of which can constitute a mental state called ‘elpis’. Elpis captures modal thinking about the future, with a focus on practical possibilities. I focus my analysis on the famous image of the painter and the scribe in the soul (39b–40c). I argue that both the painter and the scribe can form elpides. In particular, the work of the painter consists in producing phantasmata which depict future possible outcomes without necessarily assessing their likelihood. Yet, the painter depicts these outcomes as practicable for the agent, in part because his work is derived from memory and perception and in part because it involves self-representation. This characterisation of elpis suggests that ‘phantastic’ cognitive engagement with the future in the dialogue is neither idle nor concerned with making predictions. All it presupposes is that the agent deems an outcome practicable for her in future. My paper will concern Plato's account of phantasia and Aristotle's criticism of it. First, I will reconstruct Plato's account of phantasia starting from some key texts contained in Theaetetus, Sophist, Republic, and Philebus. Plato does not explore phantasia so systematically, yet he provides us with the elements to reconstruct a coherent conception of it: he proposes a two-factors model of phantasia (which is meant not just as imagination but more generally as 'appearing'), according to which phantasia is a complex mental state involving both a belief and a perception. On its own, perception is under the threshold of the truth-evaluability, so that only the doxastic component of phantasia is taken to be responsible for an appearance's being potentially true or false (see Theaetetus 184–186; Sophist 262a–c). But a doxa is the outcome of an act of thinking (dianoeisthai), which is defined as a discourse of the soul with itself (Theaetetus 189a–190a; Sophist 263e–264b), and this opens a problem for perceptual beliefs, to which 'appearances' are reduced to by Plato himself: perceptual appearence is a very exceptional type of doxastic representation indeed. Plato's position is really close to the so-called Belief-Theory of Perceptual experience developed by Armstrong 1968 and Pitcher 1970 (with some advocates nowadays, although they are a minority). Secondly, indeed, I will show how Aristotle's criticism of Plato's view in De anima III 3 is structurally analogous to the critical reactions to the Belief-Theory of perceptual experience (e.g., Crane 1988, 1990, Peacocke 1994): what is at stake in both cases is how to conceive the relation between perception and thought. According to Aristotle – as well as to the critics of the Belief-Theory of perceptual appearance in contemporary philosophy of mind – perceptual experience exhibits certain features which are incompatible with the way our system of beliefs typically works, namely, a normative, rational and holistic way. The so-called informational encapsulation, the cognitive impenetrability, and the insensitivity to collateral information, on the contrary, are structural features of perceptual appearance that can be accessed also (but not only) at a phenomenological level: in fact, our appearances are resistent to our beliefs, so that when we come to know that A is not F, A does not start appearing not-F to us, it rather keeps appearing (as though it was) F. But if Plato was right in taking phantasia as belief + perception, our doxastic life would involve contradictory beliefs on the same object at the same time: contradictory beliefs that we would know to be such! Finally, I will suggest some ideas about the way in which the debate between Plato and Aristotle may have shaped some posterior debates on the relation between perception and belief: my cursory suggestions will concern the relationship between the Epicurean two-factor model of false appearances (false belief + true perception) and the Platonic two-factor model of appearing (to a certain extent, recovered by Epicurus in such a way as to overcome Aristotle's criticism of Plato's version of it). The claim that thought depends on phantasia plays a prominent role in Aristotle’s De Anima – not least because Aristotle’s answers to some basic questions about the unity and status of the human soul directly depend on it. But what consideration is the claim based upon? What kind of objects of thought and what kind of thought is it concerned with? The paper critically examines the main existing answers and sketches out an alternative, based on the observation that (a) the primary objects of thought are for Aristotle nothing less than essences and that (b) an essence can (with a few exceptions) only be properly grasped in a complex explanatory framework. In Nicomachean Ethics VII.3, Aristotle notes that an akratic person fails to act according to their knowledge (e.g., someone who eats a sweet despite knowing it is unhealthy) because they fail to contemplate (theōrein) a particular, perceptual knowledge about the object of action—such as that featured in the minor premise “this is sweet and bad for health,” alongside the major premise “everything sweet is bad for health.” This act of contemplation is often understood as an act of attention that activates the relevant perceptual knowledge (See, e.g., Irwin 1999, p.345; and more recently, Nielsen 2020, p.161-163); without it, such knowledge remains merely potential and ineffective in practical deliberation. On the other hand, scholars have observed that, while not explicitly stated in EN VII.3, Aristotle’s psychological and biological works suggest that the akratic person’s failure also stems from a breakdown in representation. Under the sway of a dominant appetitive desire (epithumia), the akratic individual does not represent the object of action through phantasia logistikē (e.g., a conceptually rich, intellectual representation of the sweet as unhealthy), but is instead moved by phantasia aisthētikē (e.g., a more spontaneous, non-intellectual representation of the sweet as pleasant and good). (See e.g. Destrée 2007, Francis 2011) As with the act of attention, the representation provided by phantasia logistikē appears to be indispensable for activating the relevant knowledge of the object in question. In this essay, I explore how the act of attention (theōrein) relates to the function of representation (through phantasia) in both the causation of akrasia and practical deliberation more broadly. My central claim is that, in order to represent the object of action as integrated within a particular piece of knowledge, one must attend to the image (phantasma) of the object in a specific manner—one that enables the information therein to be structured and processed in alignment with the cognitive content of the practical syllogism. My argument unfolds by tracking the use of the term “to contemplate” (theōrein) in Aristotle’s psychological works, where it is consistently associated with the selective nature of attention and shown to be instrumental in shaping representation and activating knowledge. Key passages include: (1) De Anima II.1, where Aristotle describes the voluntary contemplation and activation of a chosen piece of knowledge; (2) De Anima III.8, where contemplation is linked simultaneously to an image and a corresponding thought; (3) De Memoria 1, where contemplating an image selectively leads to different representations of the object, including the representation of it as an object of thinking; and (4) De Anima III.9, where the contemplation in question is subtly situated within the process of the deliberation for action. By drawing these passages together and interpreting them in light of Nicomachean Ethics VII.3, I show how this form of attention is indispensable for the proper representation of the object of action in practical deliberation. Importantly, this form of attention—understood in relation to representation—appears to exceed the scope of Aristotle’s so-called “biased competition model” of attention, as recently reconstructed by Fiecconi (Fiecconi 2021; see also Ierodiakonou 2022). On this model, attention consists in a competition among multiple psycho-physiological movements or stimuli, resulting in different degrees of vividness in consciousness. By contrast, the theōrein form of attention does not directly involve such competition, but rather consists in the selective and deliberate processing of a single movement—namely, that of the phantasma representing the object of action. My aim is to focus on the role of phantasia in moral education based on Aristotle’s Politics VIII.5, where he argues in favor of using music to shape character (following Plato’s Republic II–III). This might come as a surprise given that character formation in Aristotle’s ethics typically goes through habituation (ἐθισμός) in virtuous actions, by repeatedly practicing such actions ourselves and learning first-hand how to improve our emotional responses and, ultimately, how to feel delight or aversion in the appropriate way. Nevertheless, we should not be surprised, since in the Ethics his aim is to show what is up to us to do for the cultivation of virtue in our souls, whereas in the Politics his aim is to show what the polis can do to support moral education. From this point of view, Politics VIII.5 speaks of a complementary habituation process (συνεθίζεσθαι) of a special sort that operates through images, likenesses and imitations of character traits, such as courage and temperance. In other words, artistic representations of virtues through melodies and rhythms, with or without the use of words—expressed by the terms ‘image’ (εἰκών), ‘likeness’ (ὁμοίωμα), ‘imitation’ (μίμημα) of feelings—are seen as contributing to the cultivation of appropriate emotional responses, especially in children. How does this work? In my view, it must be phantasia that is responsible for preserving not only the representational content of the perception of those images but also the affective component, namely the pleasure or pain that accompanies the perception of those images. Although the term phantasia or phantasma is not mentioned in Politics VIII.5 (nor anywhere in the Politics), my aim will be to show that this is what is at work in this context. In the paper, I will take Politics VIII.5 as a starting point and then examine passages in other Aristotelian works (primarily: De Anima, On Memory , as well as the Rhetoric) that allow us to see phantasia as a ‘motivational bearer’. I will then return to Politics VIII.5 and the idea that our ability to respond to real-life ethical challenges is enhanced through our emotional responses to representations of real-life ethical challenges. If indeed, as I see it, phantasia is at play in this process, then—far from being necessarily associated with error, illusion, or dreaming, as in other contexts (for instance, De Anima III.3)—it proves valuable, especially for children, to create and store in memory ‘mental images’ of things that are morally attractive or morally repellent. Along with the standard form of habituation described in the Ethics, and, later in life, this will provide a sound basis for forming desires about the right objects and for goal-directed action. Epicurus’ epistemology presents a sophisticated account of cognition rooted in empirical realism. Central to this framework is the concept of prolēpsis (πρόληψις), traditionally translated as “preconception”. While prolēpsis has long been recognised as one of Epicurus’ three criteria of truth – alongside perception and pathē (affections) –, its precise nature and function remain contested. In this paper, I argue that prolēpsis is best understood not as a static image or propositional belief akin to a general concept, but as a dynamic process of recognition that unifies and complements sensory data within the rational soul. The aim of the paper is to explore the role of imagination in the Stoic practice of premeditatio malorum (“the pre-meditation of evils”), with a focus on Seneca and Epictetus. Their paradigmatic example of this practice is the contemplation of death, either one’s own or that of a loved one. Epictetus, for instance, writes: “Let death and exile and everything that is terrible appear before your eyes every day, especially death; and you will never have anything contemptible in your thoughts or crave anything excessively” (Handbook 21). This practice is thought to yield a range of benefits: it helps us prepare ourselves, free ourselves of fears or anxieties, make the best use of the time we have. It is not obvious how we should understand this practice or what cognitive abilities it engages. However, it is reasonable to suggest that it involves the use of imagination – specifically, visual imagining. This seems a natural way to interpret Epictetus’ exhortation to “let death and exile and everything that is terrible appear before your eyes”. Indeed, this is a dominant interpretation among the Modern Stoics who, following William Irvine, refer to premeditatio malorum as “negative visualization” (A Guide to the Good Life, Oxford, 2009, ch. 4). Some authors have compared it to exposure therapy (R. Menzies and L. Whittle, "Stoicism and death acceptance: integrating Stoic philosophy in cognitive behaviour therapy for death anxiety“. Discover Psychology (2022) 2:11). On this view, this practice amounts to visually imagining possible losses or worst-case scenarios. If visual imagination plays a central role in premeditatio malorum and if this practice is central to achieving a good life and a settled mind, then it follows that imagination plays a profoundly positive role for later Stoics. On the other hand, their most explicit remarks about imagination seem to emphasize its negative aspects. It is portrayed as something that leads us astray, fosters false expectations or causes us to worry unnecessarily. As Seneca puts it, “often when no sign indicates that anything bad is on the I will explore whether and how these seemingly conflicting roles of imagination can be reconciled. Tentatively, I will propose that premeditatio malorum involves not only visual imagining but also, crucially, cognitive work with one’s judgements, i.e., assents to appearances. At the same time, I will maintain that visual imagining has a role to play in this practice. This dual account helps to address a common objection to the Stoic cognitive theory of emotions, raised already by Posidonius, that judgements might be present without corresponding emotions if one is unable to imagine a givenAbstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Thirdly, I will explore the details of Aristotle's argument in De anima III 3 and do justice to certain apparent oddities contained in it.Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
way, the mind makes up its own false imaginings” (Letters to Lucilius 13.12).
scenario. (See R. Sorabji, "Is Stoic Philosophy Helpful as Psychotherapy?" Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies, 1997, pp. 197–209.) The Stoic position, I suggest, is compatible with viewing visual imagination as a skill that ought to be cultivated and appropriately constrained.Contact:
OCTOBER 10 (Friday) MEDIEVAL
Program:
SESSION 1 (Chair: )
9:00 – 9:45
Matthias Perkams (Jena): Imagination and the Intelligence of Animals in Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas
9:45 – 10:30
Andreas Blank (Klagenfurt): Francesco Piccolomini on the Imagination of Insects
SESSION 2 (Chair: )
11:00 – 11:45
Péter Lautner: Michael of Ephesus on the Representational Capacity
11:45 – 12:30
Nick Wiltsher (St. Andrews): From Aristotle’s State to Avicenna’s Process
Lunch Break: 12:30 – 14:00
SESSION 3 (Chair: )
14:00 – 14:45
Patricia Calvario (Louvain): The Eschatological Transformation of Phantasia in the Beatific Vision
14:45 – 15:30
Luka Kuchukhidze (Tbilisi): The Epistemological and Metaphysical Dimensions of Imaginatio in Nicholas of Cusa's Thought
SESSION 4 – Chair: Dániel Schmal (RCH, Budapest)
16:00 – 16:45
Véronique Decaix (Paris): TBA
16:45 – 17:30
Vili Lähteenmäki (Oulu): TBA
Abstracts
The paper discusses Albert’s and Aquinas’s explanations of intelligent behavior of animals. Both authors agree with Aristotle’s claim that there are different degrees of intelligence in animals and explain them as well as the anthropological difference in more detail. The paper argues that Albert and Aquinas develop this theory by inserting it into a Neoplatonic framework and by applying to it their versions of Avicenna’s theory of the inner senses, assigning a prominent place to imagination, memory and experience. TBA TBA The aim of this paper is to illuminate the transition from Aristotle’s account of imagination to Avicenna’s ( Ibn Sînâ’s) by applying a distinction among contempoary views of imagination. Recently, many have argued that imagination is fundamentally a representative state (the loci classici of this view are books by Currie and Ravenscroft (2002) and Nichols and Stitch (2003)). Some have instead suggested that imagination is fundamentally a mental process (Wiltsher, 2023). In relation to this distinction, we can think of Aristotle as a representationalist, and Avicenna as a process theorist. On a credible reading, offered for example by Victor Caston, Aristotle introduces phantasia in De Anima to solve a problem: that of error in perception (Caston, 1996). It does so by providing error-prone sensory-like representations (phantasmata) that can be stored, recalled, concatenated, and otherwise manipulated by other faculties. Aristotle, then, thinks of imagination in relation to representative states. Avicenna, meanwhile, provides a quite different view in his own De Anima, despite his ostensible aim of merely interpreting Aristotle. Avicenna is concerned with a different problem: how exactly we get from perception of particulars to abstract thought. His solution, essentially, is that we do so by progressively refining perceptual representations such that they lose aspects of their particularity and become appropriate material for cognition. And the faculty which we use to do this refinement is the imagination. This claim may seem peculiar, since Avicenna in fact posits a number of putatively imaginative faculties. However, according to Hülya Yaldir (2009), these are really stages or successive operations in the process of abstraction. And it is this whole process, she thinks, that deserves the name “imagination” in Avicenna. So we do not have numerous separate faculties: we have one faculty, united by a shared function, not by a kind of representation. This is the key to seeing Avicenna as a process theorist. And with that distinction in mind, we can see why Avicenna develops this view from Aristotle’s view of phantasia. Already in Aristotle, we have the idea that imagination is a productive faculty. The obvious question to ask is from where or from what it produces; those images do not come from nowhere. The obvious answer is that the images are derived from previous, retained apprehensions. But then, if images are capable of representing novelties, this derivation cannot be straight replication: it must be a form of manipulation, be it combinatorial, abstractive, or synthetic. And once you have the idea that imagination addresses the perceptual problem by performing such manipulations, it becomes attractively efficient to suppose that imagination also solves the abstraction problem by the same method. After all, it seems as though much the same power is in play, and a faculty just is a power of mind. So the focus shifts subtly from thinking of imagination primarily in terms of the states it produces to thinking of it primarily in terms of how it produces these states. The reasoning behind this shift might, in turn, be usefully reapplied to contemporary debate between process theorists and representationalists. TBA This paper examines the multifaceted role of imaginatio within Nicholas of Cusa’s comprehensive philosophical and theological works. In the first part of the paper, I argue that Cusa establishes imaginatio as a critical cognitive faculty indispensable for the mind's engagement with, and understanding of, the fundamental structure of reality, particularly the relationship between the finite and the infinite. I posit that Cusa's imaginatio is integral to the cognitive process leading to "learned ignorance," emphasizing its active contribution to the ascent of knowledge. Subsequently, this paper substantiates imaginatio's pivotal epistemological and metaphysical function through close textual analysis of Cusa's primary works. In De Docta Ignorantia (e.g., I.11-12, II.2-3), imaginatio is shown to be essential for constructing mental models—such as the infinite sphere or the coincidence of geometric figures—which enable the intellect's initial, non-discursive apprehension of God's comprehensive unity and omnipresence. My analysis indicates that this active manipulation of conceptual images constitutes a primary cognitive operation, preparing the ground for intellectual apprehension. More specifically, in De Coniecturis (e.g., I.1, I.12-14), imaginatio is central to the method of conjecture, where the mind constructs conceptual frameworks across hierarchical levels. Through imaginative manipulation of sensible images and their proportional relationships (as Cusa delineates the ascent from sensus to imaginatio and then to ratio), this paper demonstrates that the intellect progresses from the known to the unknown, allowing human understanding to conjecturally trace the metaphysical order of the cosmos, mirroring the divine explicatio from God's complicatio. Furthermore, Cusa’s Idiota de Mente (e.g., ch. 1, 6) explicitly shows how the "layman," meditating on concrete objects, employs imaginatio to transcend physical particularity and abstract universal concepts. I contend this process reveals the imprint of divine reason within created particulars, illustrating imagination's direct, empirical, yet intellectually formative role in actualizing the mind's inherent capacity to be a "living image" or "measure" of divine truth. To further illuminate imaginatio's role, this paper integrates and builds upon key insights from contemporary scholarship on Cusa. For instance, Philipp Rosemann (2010), in his work on Cusa's metaphorical theology, critically underscores the imaginative construction inherent in apprehending abstract concepts and divine attributes, providing a framework for understanding how imaginatio contributes to Cusa's unique symbolic language. Similarly, drawing on Johannes Hoff's (2013) exploration of Cusa's analogical rationality and the complicatio/explicatio dynamic, my analysis offers a further delineation of the specific cognitive and metaphysical mechanisms by which Cusa’s imaginatio uniquely structures human understanding. Integrating these interpretations, I argue that Cusa’s imaginatio is a pivotal cognitive heuristic, supplying the symbolic and analogical frameworks necessary for the mind to approach and approximate the ultimate nature of reality. TBA TBAAbstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
OCTOBER 11 (Saturday) EARLY MODERN
Program:
SESSION 1 (Chair: )
9:00 – 9:45
Philippe Hamou (Paris): Wandering thoughts: The Early Modern Invention of Mental Life
9:45 – 10:30
Melissa Frankel (Ottawa): Beyond Scepticism: Dreams in Early Modern Philosophy
SESSION 2 (Chair: )
11:00 – 11:45
Maxime Ilou (Lyon): Children's Imagination in Malebranche: Imagination, Memory and Childhood Psychology
11:45 – 12:30
Lucia Oliveri (Münster): Fortifying the Will with Play: Leibniz on Imagination in Learning and Education
Lunch Break: 12:30 – 14:00
SESSION 3 (Chair: )
14:00 – 14:45
David Harmon (St. Andrews): Spinoza and the Physics of Imaginative Error
14:45 – 15:30
Máté Juhász (ELTE, Budapest): The Individual as Object of Imagination in Spinoza
SESSION 4 (Chair: )
16:00 – 16:45
Olivér Tóth (Heidelberg): Turning passiones Into actiones by Knowledge – Is Active Imaginative Practical Motivation in Spinoza Possible?
16:45 – 17:30
Kevin Busch (Claremont, California): The Limits of Humean Thought
Abstracts
TBA In this paper, I propose to examine the treatment of dreams by some early modern philosophical figures, and in particular, the way that dreaming, rather than being an extraordinary or deviant case, was thought to be located somewhere on a spectrum of sensory experiences that includes ordinary cases of sensation and imagination. To the extent that contemporary philosophers have been interested in early modern conceptions of dreams, the focus has overwhelmingly been on Descartes’s dream scepticism in the first Meditation. But against the narrow focus of the philosophical literature, I suggest that Descartes and many of his followers invoked considerations of dreams towards a myriad of philosophical purposes beyond thinking about scepticism and knowledge. Their treatment of dreams not only often came alongside discussions of other supposedly abnormal mental states, but also invoked wider accounts of a variety of normal sensory experiences. Descartes, for instance, links dreaming to madness and melancholia; meanwhile, his resolution of the epistemological dream concern involves not only considerations about other cognitive states, e.g., memory, but also his general account of physiology. His discussion of dreams at the end of the Meditations comes alongside a longer discussion of the general mechanisms undergirding sensation and the imagination, as well as an account of other seemingly abnormal mental phenomena such as phantom pains, which turn out to be explicable by way of the normal (rather than aberrant) laws of sensation. (Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, vol. 2, Cambridge 1985, 58–61.) Interestingly, these are the discussions, rather than dream scepticism, that many later French philosophers picked up on from Descartes. Malebranche, for instance, mentions dreams only briefly, but as part of a much more extensive discussion of sensation more generally, in which he discusses seemingly aberrant psychological cases (including, again, phantom pains and madness) at length. (Malebranche, The Search After Truth: With Elucidations of the Search After Truth, ed. T. M. Lennon and P. J. Olscamp, Cambridge, 1997, 569–572) In Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie, meanwhile, there are two philosophical entries on dreams, one of which focuses precisely on physiological accounts of different kinds of dreams (P.-J. Malouin, “Dream,” in Encyclopedia of Diderot & d’Alembert - Collaborative Translation Project, trans. S. Harris, Ann Arbor, 2007, http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.did2222.0000.878.), and the other of which links dreams to the imagination, discusses it in reference to medicine and abnormal psychology (delirium), and only briefly alludes to the connection of dreams to metaphysical philosophy (and, incidentally, does not mention scepticism at all.) (Diderot (attributed), “Dream,” in Encyclopedia of Diderot & d’Alembert) The purpose of this paper, then, is not so much to try to solve any philosophical problem about early modern accounts of dreams, but rather, to try to trace some of the ways that, for Descartes (and some others), dreams were treated as linked to ‘abnormal’ mental states, but then also to try to trace some of the ways that those ‘abnormal’ mental states were treated as not truly abnormal at all. The result, hopefully, will enable a revitalised consideration of early modern conceptions of dreams – one that may help show the significance of the philosophy of dreams beyond the narrow confines of concerns about scepticism, for understanding the mind and cognition more generally. This paper aims at providing an overview of Nicolas Malebranche's conception of children's imagination. To do this, I will draw on an internalist analysis of Book II of The search after truth, named “On Imagination”, in order to consider the function played by the analysis of children's imagination in particular. This approach leads me to defend two theses: on the one hand, the paradigmatic case of children's imagination is a revealing case, or a magnifying mirror for analyses of human imagination in general. On the other hand, Malebranche's conceptualisation of children's imagination at different stages of their development leads me to see in these texts the premises of a developmental psychology, the origin of which historiography usually attributes to Rousseau. The second book of The search after truth, still little studied, has attracted the attention of commentators who emphasise, in particular, the fundamental place of physiology in the development of Malebranche's science of man, and who comment on Malebranche's conceptual innovation about the contagion of imaginations (the way in which what is imagined by a human being is communicated to others) and on strong imaginations (individuals in particular who manage to communicate or even impose their imaginations with force, which partly explains relations of authority or domination). Nevertheless, no work has yet been done on the place of the child in this book, or in Malebranche in general. We will show that Malebranche considers the development of children's imagination, starting with the foetus, by focusing on the nature of the links – a fundamental notion that we will explain – that it has with his mother: according to Malebranche, foetuses ‘see what their mothers see’ and ‘imagine what their mothers imagine’: the child's imagination is shaped from intrauterine life, which will determine his likes and dislikes (the question of imagination thus intersects with that of memory). Once born, the specific nature of the child's link with his parents or nurses explains the exemplary contagion of imaginations, thus explaining what we would today call “social reproduction”. Malebranche's mechanistic anthropology, also based on a physiological explanation of the child (especially the characteristics of his brain fibers) and taking into account the specific nature of the links that bind him to his environment, offers a new and original conceptualisation of children's imagination at different stages of their development. The implications of this work are manifold. Firstly, from the point of view of the history of imagination, it highlights the conceptual innovation of mechanistic anthropology in the Early Modern period, in particular that of Malebranche, which articulates the theory of the imagination with a new psychophysiology. Secondly, from the perspective of Childhood Studies, it sheds light on a little-known episode in the history of childhood. Finally, from a historiographical point of view, it replaces Malebranche in the history of childhood psychology and developmental psychology, whose role has been neglected. “Human beings are never more ingenious than in inventing games; the mind is at ease here.” (“Les hommes ne sont jamais plus ingenieux que dans l'invention des jeux; l'esprit s'y trouve a son aise.” Leibniz to Pièrre Remond de Montmort, 17 January 1716, LBr. 769 Bl. 1). „ ...one can also teach serious subjects in a playful way. And so they are more effective.” („...man kan ja ernsthaffte dinge auch spielend vorbringen. Und da würcken sie beßer.“ (Aufzeichnungen nach einer Lektüre von »ZUFÄLLIGEN GEDANCKEN« 1691, A IV 4 608) Leibniz devoted most of his intellectual effort to finding remedies to the limitations of human lives, both personal and societal, with the aim of enabling individuals and communities to achieve happiness: a society comprised of happy individuals is one in which the arts, sciences, and all the positive aspects of human life flourish. He proposes various strategies to achieve this, but the “great point is the amelioration (redressement) of education, which must render virtue pleasant/agreeable in order to make it natural” (Memoire pour des personnes eclairées et de bonne intention (1692) A IV 4 615). Education’s purpose is to enlighten reason and fortify the will in the exercise of virtues by submitting will to reason. The topic of rendering the virtues pleasant is central in the educational concept that Leibniz develops since his young writings (as Nova methodus docendae discendaeque jurisprudentiae (1667)), and it receives extensive treatment until his death. In his view, virtues become desirable and pleasant when they are taught in a playful manner: play is the expedient to fortify the will in an agreeable way. Play is the best way to fortify the will, not only because it can be introduced and used from a young age, but also because it engages the subject’s conative and cognitive capacities, pleasantly forcing them to think and act, and to combine theory and praxis. Play relies on imagination as a capacity that mediates between lower and higher capacities: the material offered to the senses is transformed into input that animates the emotions (hope to win/fear of losing) and cognitive/conative capacities of the subject, prompting them to initiate something based on the sensory input (e.g. consider the shack game, where the arrangement of the pawns invites to legitimate moves). The talk will present a detailed account of Leibniz’s idea that imagination involved in play fortifies the will in a playful, and hence agreeable, way. Through this analysis, I will show that Leibniz’s proposal has implications that extend far beyond the ethical sphere. Play enables one to exercise the “ingenium”, or the ability responsible for invention. Using play in teaching and education not only results in virtues being interiorized as a second nature and disposing the subject towards goodness, but also advances science by removing impediments to the will, such as doubt, to discover truth. This will advance society by improving the arts. Spinoza's epistemology distinguishes three kinds of cognition, which correspond to varying kinds of truths and degrees of clarity: imagination, reason, and intuition. Respectively, reason and intuition procure adequate ideas by either subsuming things under common notions or by immediately understanding the necessary ontological relationship between the essences of a given individual and of God. By giving us insight into the eternal and necessary structure of reality, reason and intuition provide us with true, complete ideas. Imagination, on the other hand, is an arational cognitive faculty. Spinoza understands imagination to be constituted by what we would today call perception and memory, the mental faculties involved in generating or contemplating images. For him, imagination results from how surrounding bodies impact ours; for example, a particle strikes the eye at a certain angle, prompting one to form an idea of a remote object's location. However, since our relations to surrounding bodies are inconstant and perspectival, imagination is the source of error, falsity, and inadequate ideas. This is not to say that all ideas procured through imagination are false, but they are vulnerable to falsity. In this paper, I offer an account of this vulnerability grounded in Spinoza's sparse but suggestive physics. Specifically, I focus on a little-discussed passage from Part II of the Ethics, where Spinoza articulates a law governing oblique collisions, interactions between bodies traveling on different lines: When a body in motion strikes against another which is at rest and cannot give way, then it is reflected, so that it continues to move, and the angle of the line of the reflected motion with the surface of the body at rest which it struck against will be equal to the angle which the line of the incident motion makes with the same surface (EIIa2"). I offer an account of the role of this collision law in Spinoza's epistemology. At Ellp17d2, Spinoza invokes it to explain that an oblique collision can move a reflecting body, such that the effective angle of reflection is incongruent with the initial angle of incidence. To use the example of my eye again, if the collision of a particle with my eye itself moves some part of my eye, the effective angle of reflection will differ from the angle of incidence. As a result, I may generate an idea of an object's location that does not correspond to its actual location, since I form the idea on the basis of my body's status after the collision. On this reading, Spinoza's seemingly anomalous law of oblique collision provides a physical and metaphysical explanation for the epistemic limitations of imagination. Imagination is the source of epistemic error, not because of cognitive failure, but as a structural consequence of being a body among bodies. In my paper, I wish to share the main ideas of a chapter from my upcoming dissertation on Spinoza’s theory of interpersonal relations, including friendship and love determined by the second kind of knowledge, or imagination. The chapter is on Spinoza’s theory of affectuum imitatio, according to which our imagination of some present affect of “a thing similar to us” (res nobis similis) engenders a similar affect in ourselves (Ethics, part III, proposition 27). This doctrine of affective imitation plays a central but multifaceted role within Spinoza’s theory of human nature. Major XXth century French commentator Alexandre Matheron has claimed that, through the doctrine of the imitation of affects, Spinoza’s philosophy involves a novel way of theorizing society, politics and history. Somewhat more modestly, but nonetheless importantly, a number of Anglo-Saxon commentators have time and again emphasized the relevance of this doctrine for shielding Spinoza’s allegedly egoistic, metaphysically grounded moral psychology from being trivially false. However, despite laudation for the economy of the principle itself, Spinoza’s argument was found wanting. The doctrine apparently rests on a broader notion of contagious imagination, for the imitation of affects (affecti, the subject-matter of Spinoza’s theory of “affectivity” in the contemporary sense of the term) is argued for on the basis of the imitation of affections (affectiones, which pertain to Spinoza’s theory of sense-perception, association and empirical knowledge), which encompasses the former. Moreover, the claim to contagious imagination is argued for through a rather challenging inference from the general theory of imagination to it becoming further bodily assimilation of the imagining subject to the imagined object under the assumption of preexisting similarity. However, Spinoza provides no account of the relevant sense of similarity, nor does he indicate the sufficient degree. Commentators are even divided on the rather fundamental question of whether the similarity in question was meant to be entirely real or (at least partly) imaginary. Did the author of the Ethics assume that his intended readers will relate it to the objective features of interacting bodies? Or was he expecting that they will consider the similarity itself a product of imagination, prone to confusion and misrepresentation? Thence the bewilderment of many astute readers. Matheron himself calls the deduction “fort curieuse”, and remarks – concerning the nature and degree of similarity required – that “Sans doute serait-il quelque peu embarrassant d’entrer dans les details” (Individu et communauté [1988], 154-5). Similarly, while Jonathan Bennett praises “This use by Spinoza of the concept of similarity” as “a brilliant metaphysical tour de force”, he finds Spinoza’s discursive brevity as painful here as anywhere in the Ethics: “He says nothing about how much similarity is needed to bring his theory into play” (see A Study [1984], 280-1, cf. Broad: Five Types [1967], 37-38 and Della Rocca: “Egoism and Imitation” [2004], 140). I aim to take a fresh look at this doctrine and the difficulties involved, especially those that concern the notion of similarity. I follow Justin Steinberg (“Imitation, Representation, and Humanity” [2013]) in maintaining that the correct interpretation must be based on a more robust consideration of the background theory of imagination. However, my way of bringing in that theory is slightly different from his. Within reconstructing the key ideas of Spinoza’s general theory of imagination, I place a special emphasis on the peculiar case of representing a thing like us. In short, I wish to shed more light on the all-important imitation doctrine by investigating how imagining another human individual (and imagining them as such) supposedly works in Spinoza. Spinoza identifies imagination with sense perception (E2p15–17) and memory (E2p18), which are identified as the grounds of the first kind of knowledge: knowledge from experience and knowledge from testimony (E2p40s2). He states that the first kind of knowledge is the only cause of falsity (E2p41) and never teaches us to distinguish the true from the false (E2p42). Given Spinoza’s identification of the will and the intellect (E2p48–49), ideas of imagination are not only representations of reality but also motivations for action. For human beings, virtue is the power by which they persevere in their being; power is defined by the human being’s ability to engage in actiones (E4d8). Actiones, unlike passiones, are the human being’s effects that can be understood through the essence of the human being – i.e., their power – alone (E3d2). Actiones follow from the mind’s adequate ideas alone (E3p1) – ideas that do teach us to distinguish the true from the false (E2p43) – and adequate ideas give rise to actiones but never passiones (E3p3). Actiones always lead to an increase in the human being’s power (E3p4), i.e., virtue, and are always experienced as joyful affects (E3d3), whereas passiones can lead to the human being’s destruction and are experienced as joy or sadness. Spinoza flatly denies the existence of any normative consideration transcendent to the conative motivational structure constituting the given human being’s essence (E3p9s), but affirms that this structure is constituted by both adequate and inadequate ideas (E3p9d). These considerations together might suggest that the human being’s motivational structure is characterized by an ineliminable duality between sensuous motivations accompanied by the interplay of joy and sadness characterizing the satisfaction of egoistic desires and intelligible motivations accompanied by the joyful experience of the human being’s eternal essence determining their action (E5p29–32) (Della Rocca 2008; Renz 2022; Youpa 2009; Newlands 2018; Perler 2011). But how to read Spinoza’s claim in E5p3 that passiones turn into actiones through knowledge? Are passiones replaced by actiones? In this paper, I argue that this cannot be the case. Imaginations do not teach us to distinguish true from false in isolation (Toth 2025), but they constitute the matter of the human motivational structure: without imaginations, the human being did not have the ability to desire to engage in spatially and temporally located actions. In isolation, imaginations do not have transparent evidential power and can warrant theoretical and practical inferences that are in fact “conclusions without premises” (E2p28d). However, the human mind has the power to give its imaginations the intelligible form of a coherent structure, in which case their evidential power becomes transparent and their motivational power reduced to the desire of what is necessary (Toth early view). If the human subject achieves self-knowledge (Carlisle 2017), active imaginative practical motivation is possible. In this case, the human subject understands their desire to do x as being causally necessitated by their essence, i.e., by their desire: the desire is thus self-justifying. Carlisle, Clare. 2017. “Spinoza’s Acquiescentia.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 55 (2): 209–36. https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2017.0027. Hume has been credited with ushering in the naturalistic approach to mental representation (see, e.g., J. Cottrell “Hume on mental representation and intentionality”). Only fairly recently has his own account of mental representation received serious attention. Notable attempts at a systematic interpretation of Hume’s account can be found in work by Don Garrett (“Hume’s naturalistic theory of representation”; Hume), Karl Schafer (“Hume’s Unified Theory of Mental Representation”), and David Landy (Kant’s Inferentialism: The Case Against Hume, Ch. 2; “Recent Scholarship on Hume’s Theory of Mental Representation”). We have these commentators to thank for a clearer picture of Humean mental representation—of what constitutes it, how it comes about, and its role in various mental operations like causal inference and moral judgment. Yet one important aspect of Hume’s account remains a source of interpretive controversy. Hume took thought to involve mentally representing an entity with a grasp of some of its intrinsic nature. He also held that our thoughts (“ideas”) ultimately “copy,” or exactly resemble and derive from, our sensory representations (“impressions”); call this ‘the Copy Principle’. The question is how, if it all, the Copy Principle limits what we can think. This question has been addressed indirectly in the literature on Hume’s causal metaphysics. Proponents of the “Old Hume” take the Copy Principle to entail a stronger constraint on our thought, one that precludes any thought of—and so realism about—a mind-independent causal power over and above the fact that objects, events, or states of one type are always followed by those of another. (See Winkler “The New Hume” and Millican “Hume as a Regularity Theorist”. This view has dominated outside of Hume scholarship. See, e.g., Mackie The Cement of the Universe, Stroud Hume, Lewis Philosophical Papers, vol. II, Woolhouse The Empiricists, Blackburn “Hume and Thick Connexions”, and Ellis (“Causal Laws and Singular Causation”). Proponents of the “New Hume”, however, assume that the Copy Principle entails either no constraint on our thought or one that allowed Hume to affirm the existence of causal powers even while denying our ability to conceive or know of them (See Wright The Sceptical Realism of David Hume, Craig The Mind of God and the Works of Man, Strawson The Secret Connexion: Causation, Realism, and David Hume, and Kail Projection and Realism in Hume’s Philosophy). I address the question head-on, and in two broad stages. First, I identify a tension between Hume’s apparent applications of a stronger copy-based constraint and his allowance for thoughts that violate this constraint. Second, I offer Hume a way out via a weaker copy-based constraint that permits both the relevant thoughts and skepticism about our representational capacities. In balancing these seemingly contrary aspects of his system, my proposal is the most plausible among charitable interpretations of Hume. And, if correct, it illuminates the varieties of Humean thought, along with the nuances of Hume’s semantic skepticism. §2 clarifies the nature of Humean thought. For Hume, S thinks of particular intentional object x if and only if: (i) S forms an idea i; and (ii) i represents with some resemblance x. §3 flags Hume’s apparent applications of a stronger copy-based constraint on our thought, and identifies candidates for this stronger constraint: STRONG COPY CONSTRAINT S thinks of x only if S forms an idea i that copies an impression exactly resembling x. STRONG COPY CONSTRAINT* S thinks of x only if S forms an idea i with parts that copy impressions exactly resembling parts of x, and i at least somewhat resembles x in the spatiotemporal arrangement of these parts. MODERATE COPY CONSTRAINT S thinks of x only if S forms an idea i with parts that copy impressions exactly resembling parts of x. §4 argues that each such candidate precludes thoughts Hume otherwise permitted: fictional and radically imperfect thoughts, and thoughts of a spatiotemporal minimum and of an invisible and intangible distance. §5 derives from these thoughts a weaker copy-based constraint: WEAK COPY CONSTRAINT S thinks of x only if S forms an idea i with parts that copy impressions at least inexactly resembling parts of x to a sufficient degree. §5 finishes by reconciling this constraint with various limitations on thought.Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Abstract:
References:
Della Rocca, Michael. 2008. Spinoza. New York: Routledge.
Newlands, Samuel. 2018. Reconceiving Spinoza. Oxford University Press.
Perler, Dominik. 2011. Transformationen der Gefühle: Philosophische Emotionstheorien 1270-1670. 1. Edition. Fischer Verlag.
Renz, Ursula. 2022. “Spinoza on the Good Life for Humans.” In Human: A History, edited by Karolina Hübner, 196–219. Oxford Philosophical Concepts. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Toth, Oliver Istvan. 2025. “The Possibility of Knowing the Essence of Bodies through Scientific Experiments in Spinoza’s Controversy with Boyle.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 33 (1): 86–110. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2024.2346176.
———. early view. “Adequacy as an Epistemically Just Social Practice in Spinoza’s Philosophy.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12618.
Youpa, Andrew. 2009. “Spinoza’s Theory of the Good.” In The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza’s Ethics, edited by Olli Koistinen, 242–57. New York: Cambridge University Press.Contact:
Abstract:
Contact:
Venue
Research Centre for the Humanities
Room: TBA
Registration
The conference is free and in-person only. Registration is needed before the event. Please indicate the day that you will participate in an email to the organisers.
Please register before the 2. October.
Registration